Fundamental sequence (set theory)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In set theory, a mathematical discipline, a fundamental sequence is a cofinal sequence of ordinals all below a given limit ordinal. Depending on author, fundamental sequences may be restricted to ω-sequences only[1] or permit fundamental sequences of length .[2] The nth element of the fundamental sequence of is commonly denoted ,[2] although it may be denoted [3] or .[4] Additionally, some authors may allow fundamental sequences to be defined on successor ordinals.[5] The term dates back to (at the latest) Veblen's construction of normal functions , while the concept dates back to Hardy's 1904 attempt to construct a set of cardinality .[6]

Definition[edit]

Given an ordinal , a fundamental sequence for is a sequence such that and .[1] An additional restriction may be that the sequence of ordinals must be strictly increasing.[7]

Examples[edit]

The following is a common assignment of fundamental sequences to all limit ordinals .[8][4][3]

  • for limit ordinals
  • for .

This is very similar to the system used in the Wainer hierarchy.[7]

Usage[edit]

Fundamental sequences arise in some settings of definitions of large countable ordinals, definitions of hierarchies of fast-growing functions, and proof theory. Bachmann defined a hierarchy of functions in 1950, providing a system of names for ordinals up to what is now known as the Bachmann–Howard ordinal, by defining fundamental sequences for namable ordinals below .[9] This system was subsequently simplified by Feferman and Aczel to reduce the reliance on fundamental sequences.[10]

The fast-growing hierarchy, Hardy hierarchy, and slow-growing hierarchy of functions are all defined via a chosen system of fundamental sequences up to a given ordinal. The fast-growing hierarchy is closely related to the Hardy hierarchy, which is used in proof theory along with the slow-growing hierarchy to majorize the provably computable functions of a given theory.[8][11]

Additional conditions[edit]

A system of fundamental sequences up to is said to have the Bachmann property if for all ordinals in the domain of the system and for all , . If a system of fundamental sequences has the Bachmann property, all the functions in its associated fast-growing hierarchy are monotone, and eventually dominates when .[7]

References[edit]

  1. ^ a b M. Rathjen, The Art of Ordinal Analysis (2006), pp. 9–10. Accessed 8 May 2023.
  2. ^ a b W. Buchholz, A survey on ordinal notations around the Bachmann-Howard ordinal (2017), p.2. Accessed 8 May 2023.
  3. ^ a b W. Buchholz, S. Wainer, Provably Computable Functions and the Fast Growing Hierarchy (1987), Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 65 (pp. 180–181).
  4. ^ a b A. Freund, F. Pakhomov, Short Proofs for Slow Consistency (2020). Accessed 8 May 2023.
  5. ^ W. Buchholz, A. Cichon, A. Weiermann, A Uniform Approach to Fundamental Sequences and Hierarchies (1994), Mathematical Logic Quarterly, vol. 40, pp.273–285.
  6. ^ O. Veblen, Continuous Increasing Functions of Finite and Transfinite Ordinals (1908).
  7. ^ a b c H. J. Prömel, W. Thumser, B. Voigt, "Fast growing functions and Ramsey theorems" (1991), Discrete Mathematics vol. 95, pp. 341–358.
  8. ^ a b A. Weiermann, Classifying the Provably Total Functions of PA (2006), Bulletin of Symbolic Logic vol. 12 no. 2, pp. 177–190.
  9. ^ J. Bridge, A Simplification of the Bachmann Method for Generating Large Countable Ordinals
  10. ^ S. Feferman, The proof theory of classical and constructive inductive definitions. A 40 year saga, 1968-2008. (2008). Accessed 8 May 2023.
  11. ^ T. Arai, A slow-growing analogue to Buchholz's proof (1991), Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 54, pp. 101–120.